Main
Rousseau: A Very Short Introduction
Rousseau: A Very Short Introduction
Robert Wokler
0 /
5.0
How much do you like this book?
What’s the quality of the file?
Download the book for quality assessment
What’s the quality of the downloaded files?
One of the most profound thinkers of modern history, Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-78) was a central figure of the European Enlightenment. He was also its most formidable critic, condemning the political, economic, theological, and sexual trappings of civilization along lines that would excite the enthusiasm of romantic individualists and radical revolutionaries alike. In this study of Rousseau's life and works, Robert Wolker shows how his philosophy of history, his theories of music and politics, his fiction, educational, and religious writings, and even his botany, were all inspired by revolutionary ideals of mankind's self-realization in a condition of unfettered freedom. He explains how, in regressing to classical republicanism, ancient mythology, direct communication with God, and solitude, Rousseau anticipated some post-modernist rejections of the Enlightenment as well.
Year:
2001
Publisher:
Oxford University Press, USA
Language:
english
Pages:
193
ISBN 10:
0192801988
ISBN 13:
9780192801982
Series:
Very Short Introductions
File:
PDF, 3.62 MB
Your tags:
Download (pdf, 3.62 MB)
- Open in Browser
- Checking other formats...
- Convert to EPUB
- Convert to FB2
- Convert to MOBI
- Convert to TXT
- Convert to RTF
- Converted file can differ from the original. If possible, download the file in its original format.
The file will be sent to your email address. It may take up to 1-5 minutes before you receive it.
The file will be sent to your Kindle account. It may takes up to 1-5 minutes before you received it.
Please note: you need to verify every book you want to send to your Kindle. Check your mailbox for the verification email from Amazon Kindle.
Please note: you need to verify every book you want to send to your Kindle. Check your mailbox for the verification email from Amazon Kindle.
Conversion to is in progress
Conversion to is failed
You may be interested in Powered by Rec2Me
Most frequent terms
rousseau519
political132
discourse132
music84
liberty76
moral71
civil71
writings63
paris61
emile59
arts59
sciences55
letter52
citizens51
geneva51
french51
religion46
remarks46
jean45
century44
virtue43
locke42
hobbes42
claims41
persons39
culture38
freedom36
letters34
france33
equality32
citizen31
essay30
sophie30
politics28
diderot28
laws28
madame27
republic27
species27
faith27
Related Booklists
0 comments
You can write a book review and share your experiences. Other readers will always be interested in your opinion of the books you've read. Whether you've loved the book or not, if you give your honest and detailed thoughts then people will find new books that are right for them.
1
|
2
|
Rousseau: A Very Short Introduction ‘Robert Wokler presents the reader with an impressive overview of Rousseau and his works, demonstrating his mastery not only of the major writings, but also of numerous minor ones, which often throw important light on the author’s thinking.’ Jean Bloch, French Studies ‘One of the best-informed, most balanced, short general introductions to Rousseau . . . in English. . . . Wokler’s study leaves a vivid impression of Rousseau’s uniqueness and originality as a thinker.’ Graeme Garrard, History of Political Thought ‘Wokler’s Rousseau provides a succinct yet remarkably comprehensive and reliable overview of the whole of Rousseau’s œuvre. . . . He guides the reader briskly, confidently, but never obtrusively.’ Victor Gourevitch, Political Theory Very Short Introductions are for anyone wanting a stimulating and accessible way in to a new subject. They are written by experts, and have been published in more than 25 languages worldwide. The series began in 1995, and now represents a wide variety of topics in history, philosophy, religion, science, and the humanities. Over the next few years it will grow to a library of around 200 volumes – a Very Short Introduction to everything from ancient Egypt and Indian philosophy to conceptual art and cosmology. Very Short Introductions available now: ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY Julia Annas THE ANGLO-SAXON AGE John Blair ANIMAL RIGHTS David DeGrazia ARCHAEOLOGY Paul Bahn ARCHITECTURE Andrew Ballantyne ARISTOTLE Jonathan Barnes ART HISTORY Dana Arnold ART THEORY Cynthia Freeland THE HISTORY OF ASTRONOMY Michael Hoskin Atheism Julian Baggini Augustine Henry Chadwick BARTHES Jonathan Culler THE BIBLE John Riches BRITISH POLITICS Anthony Wright Buddha Michael Carrithers BUDDHISM Damien Keown CAPITALISM James Fulcher THE CELTS Barry Cunliffe CHOICE THEORY Michael Allingham CHRISTIAN ART Beth Williamson CLASSICS Mary Beard and John Henderson CLAUSEWITZ Michael Howard THE COLD WAR Robert McMahon Continental Philosophy Simon Critchley COSMOLOGY Peter Col; es CRYPTOGRAPHY Fred Piper and Sean Murphy DADA AND SURREALISM David Hopkins Darwin Jonathan Howard Democracy Bernard Crick DESCARTES Tom Sorell DRUGS Leslie Iversen THE EARTH Martin Redfern EGYPTIAN MYTHOLOGY Geraldine Pinch EIGHTEENTH-CENTURY BRITAIN Paul Langford THE ELEMENTS Philip Ball EMOTION Dylan Evans EMPIRE Stephen Howe ENGELS Terrell Carver Ethics Simon Blackburn The European Union John Pinder EVOLUTION Brian and Deborah Charlesworth FASCISM Kevin Passmore THE FRENCH REVOLUTION William Doyle Freud Anthony Storr Galileo Stillman Drake Gandhi Bhikhu Parekh GLOBALIZATION Manfred Steger HEGEL Peter Singer HEIDEGGER Michael Inwood HINDUISM Kim Knott HISTORY John H. Arnold HOBBES Richard Tuck HUME A. J. Ayer IDEOLOGY Michael Freeden Indian Philosophy Sue Hamilton Intelligence Ian J. Deary ISLAM Malise Ruthven JUDAISM Norman Solomon Jung Anthony Stevens KANT Roger Scruton KIERKEGAARD Patrick Gardiner THE KORAN Michael Cook LINGUISTICS Peter Matthews LITERARY THEORY Jonathan Culler LOCKE John Dunn LOGIC Graham Priest MACHIAVELLI Quentin Skinner MARX Peter Singer MATHEMATICS Timothy Gowers MEDIEVAL BRITAIN John Gillingham and Ralph A. Griffiths MODERN IRELAND Senia Pašeta MOLECULES Philip Ball MUSIC Nicholas Cook NIETZSCHE Michael Tanner NINETEENTH-CENTURY BRITAIN Christopher Harvie and H. C. G. Matthew NORTHERN IRELAND Marc Mulholland paul E. P. Sanders Philosophy Edward Craig PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Samir Okasha PLATO Julia Annas POLITICS Kenneth Minogue POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY David Miller POSTCOLONIALISM Robert Young POSTMODERNISM Christopher Butler POSTSTRUCTURALISM Catherine Belsey PREHISTORY Chris Gosden PRESOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY Catherine Osborne Psychology Gillian Butler and Freda McManus QUANTUM THEORY John Polkinghorne ROMAN BRITAIN Peter Salway ROUSSEAU Robert Wokler RUSSELL A. C. Grayling RUSSIAN LITERATURE Catriona Kelly THE RUSSIAN REVOLUTION S. A. Smith SCHIZOPHRENIA Chris Frith and Eve Johnstone SCHOPENHAUER Christopher Janaway SHAKESPEARE Germaine Greer SOCIAL AND CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY John Monaghan and Peter Just SOCIOLOGY Steve Bruce Socrates C. C. W. Taylor SPINOZA Roger Scruton STUART BRITAIN John Morrill TERRORISM Charles Townshend THEOLOGY David F. Ford THE TUDORS John Guy TWENTIETH-CENTURY BRITAIN Kenneth O. Morgan Wittgenstein A. C. Grayling WORLD MUSIC Philip Bohlman Available soon: AFRICAN HISTORY John Parker and Richard Rathbone ANCIENT EGYPT Ian Shaw THE BRAIN Michael O’Shea BUDDHIST ETHICS Damien Keown CHAOS Leonard Smith CHRISTIANITY Linda Woodhead CITIZENSHIP Richard Bellamy CLASSICAL ARCHITECTURE Robert Tavernor CLONING Arlene Judith Klotzko CONTEMPORARY ART Julian Stallabrass THE CRUSADES Christopher Tyerman Derrida Simon Glendinning DESIGN John Heskett Dinosaurs David Norman DREAMING J. Allan Hobson ECONOMICS Partha Dasgupta THE END OF THE WORLD Bill McGuire EXISTENTIALISM Thomas Flynn THE FIRST WORLD WAR Michael Howard FREE WILL Thomas Pink FUNDAMENTALISM Malise Ruthven Habermas Gordon Finlayson HIEROGLYPHS Penelope Wilson HIROSHIMA B. R. Tomlinson HUMAN EVOLUTION Bernard Wood INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS Paul Wilkinson JAZZ Brian Morton MANDELA Tom Lodge MEDICAL ETHICS Tony Hope THE MIND Martin Davies Myth Robert Segal NATIONALISM Steven Grosby PERCEPTION Richard Gregory PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Jack Copeland and Diane Proudfoot PHOTOGRAPHY Steve Edwards THE RAJ Denis Judd THE RENAISSANCE Jerry Brotton RENAISSANCE ART Geraldine Johnson SARTRE Christina Howells THE SPANISH CIVIL WAR Helen Graham TRAGEDY Adrian Poole THE TWENTIETH CENTURY Martin Conway For more information visit our web site www.oup.co.uk/vsi Robert Wokler ROUSSEAU A Very Short Introduction 1 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford o x 2 6 d p Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Bangkok Buenos Aires Cape Town Chennai Dar es Salaam Delhi Hong Kong Istanbul Karachi Kolkata Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Mumbai Nairobi São Paulo Shanghai Taipei Tokyo Toronto Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York © Robert Wokler 1995, 2001 The moral rights of the author have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published 1995 as an Oxford University Press paperback Reissued with corrections 1996 First published as a Very Short Introduction 2001 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organizations. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Data available ISBN 13.. 978–0–19–280198–2 ISBN 10.. 0–19–280198–8 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 Typeset by RefineCatch Ltd, Bungay, Suffolk Printed in Great Britain by TJ International Ltd., Padstow, Cornwall In memory of Isaiah Berlin This page intentionally left blank Acknowledgements This work required not very much longer to complete than the eight weeks originally anticipated, but those weeks were assembled over a period of not much less than eight years. I have adapted a few pages from earlier publications, as follows: from ‘Rousseau’, in Political Thought from Plato to Nato (London, 1984), in chapter 1; from ‘The Discours sur les sciences et les arts and its Offspring’, in Reappraisals of Rousseau, ed. S. Harvey, M. Hobson, et al. (Manchester, 1980), and ‘Rousseau on Rameau and Revolution’, in Studies in the Eighteenth Century, vol. iv, ed. R. F. Brissenden and J. C. Eade (Canberra, 1979), in chapter 2; and from ‘Rousseau’s Two Concepts of Liberty’ in Lives, Liberties and the Public Good, ed. G. Feaver and F. Rosen (London, 1987), in chapter 4. Wherever possible, I have tried to incorporate corrections or improvements kindly drawn to my notice by John Hope Mason and Quentin Skinner. For his unimaginably patient forbearance in permitting me to attend to other publishing crises as they arose, and for his meticulous refinements of my style, I am indebted to Sir Keith Thomas. For their unstinting encouragement beyond all reasonable call of duty, my thanks are also due to my editors, Susie Casement and Catherine Clarke, at the Oxford University Press. For preparing a presentable typescript in the format required, I am grateful to Marilyn Dunn and Karen Hall. November 1993 I have taken the opportunity afforded by the addition of illustrations to this text to alter a few details, some for the sake of clarity, as well as to correct two errors drawn to my notice by my Japanese translator, Shuji Yamamoto. The appearance in recent years of new editions of Rousseau’s writings in both French and English has encouraged me to revise or append numerous references. Certain themes, particularly in chapters 1, 3, and 4, have been enlarged. Chapter 6, as close to emulating Rousseau’s own style as was in my power, subject also to the constraints of another language and the requirements of a work of contextual interpretation, includes fractionally more material on music. March 2001 Contents List of illustrations xiii Abbreviations 1 2 3 4 5 6 xvii The life and times of a citizen of Geneva 1 Culture, music, and the corruption of morals 23 Human nature and civil society 44 Liberty, virtue, and citizenship 71 Religion, education, and sexuality Vagabond reverie 131 Further reading 151 Index 161 101 This page intentionally left blank List of illustrations 1 A view of Geneva around 6 1720 by Robert Gardelle 2 3 attributed to Greuze Bibliothèque de Genève Collection Gérald Maurois, Paris Photo: Foliot Photo: Foliot Silhouette of Thérèse 7 Levasseur 5 8 Engraved title-page of Le Devin du village 9 engraved by Désiré Title-page of the second edition of the Lettre sur 14 la musique française Photo: Foliot 38 From the library of Robert Wokler Henry Fuseli’s frontispiece to his own Remarks on the Writings and Conduct of British Library 11826.aaa.14 28 Musée du Louvre © Archivo Iconografico, SA/Corbis View of L’Ermitage J. J. Rousseau Portrait of Diderot by Van Loo 8 Photo: Foliot 5 26 Photo: Foliot Photo: Foliot after Gautier Frontispiece and titleles sciences et les arts Chaalis 4 20 page of the Discours sur Institut de France, Musée de 3 Portrait of Rousseau 16 10 Manuscript title-page of Du principe de la mélodie Bibliothèque de Neuchâtel, Ms R 60 42 11 Frontispiece and 18 title-page of the Discours sur l’inégalité Leaf from the Manuscrit Favre 46 106 Bibliothèque de Genève, Ms R 90, reproduced from Pierre-Maurice Photo: Foliot Masson (ed.), La ‘Profession de foi du 12 Portrait of Buffon vicaire Savoyard’ de Rousseau 59 (Fribourg and Paris, 1914) © Bettmann/Corbis 13 19 Figure 1 from Edward Tyson’s Orang-Outang Héloïse by Gravelot 61 111 From the library of Robert Wokler Bridgeman Art Library, London 14 Plate 10 from La Nouvelle 20 Leaf from Book I, ch. iii of Frontispiece and title-page the Manuscrit de Genève 73 of Émile Bibliothèque de Genève, From the library of Robert Wokler 120 Ms.fr.225 21 Photo: Foliot ‘Le premier baiser de l’amour’ by Moreau le 15 Title-page of the Contrat social jeune 83 127 Photo: AKG London Photo: Foliot 22 16 Madame d’Houdetot by Title-page of the Corot Gouvernement de Bibliothèque Nationale, Paris Pologne 134 Photo: Foliot 94 Photo: Foliot 23 17 ‘Air chinois’ from the Rousseau’s tomb on the Dictionnaire de musique 139 Île des peupliers, from From the library of Robert Wokler an engraving by Moreau le jeune Photo: Foliot 99 24 Rousseau herborizing by Mayer Photo: Foliot 140 25 Portrait of Madame 27 de Warens in a yeux toute sa magnificence’ nineteenth-century engraving by Leroux by Moreau le jeune 142 Bibliothèque Nationale, Paris Photo: AKG London 26 Portrait of Rousseau by Ramsay National Gallery of Scotland, Edinburgh Photo: Annan, Glasgow ‘La nature étalait à nos 146 148 From the library of Robert Wokler This page intentionally left blank Abbreviations A Rousseau, Politics and the Arts: Letter to M. d’Alembert on the Theatre, trans. with notes and an introduction by Allan Bloom (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1977) (first published in this format in 1960) C Rousseau, The Confessions, trans. and with an introduction by J. M. Cohen (London: Penguin Books, 1953) E Rousseau, Emile, or On Education, introduction, trans., and notes by Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books, 1979) G Rousseau, Discourses and Other Early Political Writings, ed., trans., and annotated by Victor Gourevitch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997) H Rousseau on International Relations, ed. Stanley Hoffmann and David Fidler (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991) J Rousseau, Julie, or the New Héloïse, trans. and annotated by Philip Stewart and Jean Vaché (Hanover, NH: University Press of New England, 1997) L Rousseau, Correspondance complète, ed. and annotated by R. A. Leigh (Geneva and Oxford: The Voltaire Foundation, 1965–98) P Rousseau, Œuvres complètes, ed. B. Gagnebin, M. Raymond, et al. (Paris: Gallimard, Bibliothèque de la Pléiade, 1959–95) R Rousseau, Reveries of the Solitary Walker, trans. with an introduction by Peter France (London: Penguin Books, 1979) S Rousseau, The Social Contract and Other Later Political Writings, ed., trans., and annotated by Victor Gourevitch (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997) Only the most accessible English editions of Rousseau’s works are cited, and I have often preferred my own translation while nevertheless pointing to the location of another. All references to the Social Contract are to its internal books and chapters only. All references to the Correspondance complète are to a letter number. Chapter 1 The life and times of a citizen of Geneva Together with Montesquieu, Hume, Smith, and Kant among his contemporaries, Rousseau has exerted the most profound influence on modern European intellectual history, perhaps even surpassing anyone else of his day. No other eighteenth-century thinker contributed more major writings in so wide a range of subjects and forms, nor wrote with such sustained passion and eloquence. No one else managed through both his works and his life to excite or disturb public imagination so deeply. Almost alone among the seminal figures of the Enlightenment, he subjected the main currents of the world he inhabited to the most inspired censure, even while channelling their direction, and when French Revolutionary leaders later seized their opportunity to ignite the unity of political practice and theory, it was to his doctrines above all that they professed their allegiance. Like most distinguished men in his world’s republic of letters, Rousseau of course had many interests apart from politics. He was a much-admired composer and the author of a substantial and learned dictionary of music, a subject which perhaps claimed more of his attention throughout his life than any other. While a number of his most important early writings dealt with the arts and sciences and the philosophy of history, the main enthusiasm of his later years proved to be botany, to which he devoted a collection of letters that in translation was to prove a popular textbook in England. His Reveries of the Solitary 1 Walker were to spark an explosion of Romantic naturalism throughout Europe in the late eighteenth century, while his New Héloïse was the most widely read novel of his age. His Confessions, moreover, comprise the most important work of autobiography since that of St Augustine, and his Emile the most significant work on education after Plato’s Republic. Yet it is as a moralist and political thinker that he achieved his greatest distinction. His birthplace and early childhood were to leave deep impressions upon his life and the development of his thought. He was born in 1712, in Geneva, a small Calvinist country surrounded by large, predominantly Catholic, nations; a mountainous state protected from invasion by natural barriers and the political culture of its citizens; above all, a republic in the midst of duchies and monarchies. When Rousseau would Rousseau later describe the Savoyard vicar of Emile as professing his faith to a benign god of Nature rather than Scriptures, on a hill overlooking a city, he conceived an image of man’s direct communion with his maker such as could be shared by few of the inhabitants of the other cities he knew. In their opposition to arbitrary government and the privileges of a venal aristocracy, many of the philosophes of the eighteenth century regarded progressive monarchs as allies in the cause of reform. Rousseau, however, showed none of the confidence of his contemporaries in the prospects of enlightened absolutism. Whereas a radical commitment, tempered by fear of censorship, inspired Diderot, Voltaire, and others to publish their writings anonymously, he took every opportunity to sign his works ‘Citizen of Geneva’, and ceased to do so only after he was convinced that his compatriots had irredeemably lost their way. No other figure of the Enlightenment was more hostile to the course that political civilization had taken and at the same time so proud of his political identity. Rousseau’s mother died just after giving birth to him, and responsibility for his upbringing thus fell to his father, a watchmaker of romantic and irascible temperament, who inspired in him a love of Nature and books, 2 especially the classics and history. He never received a formal education, and he occasionally appeared to compensate for that deficiency by annotating his writings with lengthy footnotes which acknowledged sources that his better-schooled contemporaries scarcely troubled to cite. But his mother had inherited a large library, and his well-read father encouraged the young Rousseau’s own fascination with literature, in a cultivated manner which in his Confessions Rousseau later judged distinctive of Genevan artisans by contrast with those of other countries. It was from his father that he also inherited much of his zealous devotion to his birthplace, where, as he would be told, ‘all men are brothers’ and ‘joy and heaven reign’. At least two of his principal works, the Letter to d’Alembert on the Theatre of 1758 and his Letters from the Mountain of 1764, were to be devoted mainly to the culture or political system of his native city, and he was to remark that his Social Contract itself had been designed to portray the noble principles of that state. Nowhere in his writings is his conception of political fraternity more richly drawn than in his Letter to d’Alembert, when he recalls the convivial celebrations in the open air of a Genevan military regiment which had fired his imagination as a boy (P v 123–4 n; A 135–6 n). 3 The life and times of a citizen of Geneva 1. A view of Geneva around 1720 by Robert Gardelle. His attachment to his father and to the city of his birth did not, however, overcome the loss of his mother. When only fifteen, he was introduced to a Swiss baroness, Madame de Warens, who lived at Annecy in the Duchy of Savoy, just west of Geneva. Madame de Warens had by the still tender age of twenty-nine already made something of a career of converting Protestant refugees to Catholicism, and she brought Rousseau into her home and her bosom with an intimate hospitality that accorded well with his own rapturous enthusiasm. For the next ten years, first at Annecy and then Chambéry and finally in the idyllic retreat of the valley of Les Charmettes, he was to become both her lover and pupil. With her guidance and some assistance from her own patrons and religious confessors, he completed his education, especially in philosophy and modern literature, of which he had had little knowledge before, and began to contemplate a career as a writer. Partly inspired Rousseau by Madame de Warens’ pietist enthusiasms, furthermore, Rousseau formed an attachment to the Deity and to the marvels of His Creation which was to distinguish his religious beliefs from those of most of his contemporaries among the philosophes, who were either atheists or sceptics and suspicious of his zealotry, regarding it as akin to the mystical superstitions of a clerical Church that they aimed to bring down. Throughout their time as lovers, and for the rest of his life, Rousseau was to call Madame de Warens his maman, ascribing to her those qualities of sweetness, grace, and beauty which, as a motherless child, he longed to find in all the women under whose spell he was later to fall. Thérèse Levasseur, with whom he lived from about 1745 until his death, and whom he was eventually to marry, was a somewhat less attractive and far less educated woman, who despite her originally compelling unspoiled freshness never came to command his affections in the same way. Rather in need of maternal care as well as sexual gratification from both of the leading women in his life, he could never tolerate a family of his own, and he abandoned the five children he had by Thérèse to the uncertain fate of a public orphanage. Rousseau would later claim that he 4 had been too impoverished to care for his children properly, but his own conduct towards them filled him with remorse and shame. It certainly made readers wonder how he could write so sublime a treatise on the education of children as Emile, which may in some respects be read as a work of personal atonement. To this day, his abandonment of his children has coloured the popular image of his character far more than any of his other traits. He was also to prove less solicitous than he might have been of the needs of Madame de Warens, when in the 1750s she fell into a condition of extreme financial hardship and was even forced to register as a pauper. She was to die, with no relief from her poverty, and no contact anxieties for his own safety following the denunciation of his writings by 2. Silhouette of Thérèse Levasseur. 5 The life and times of a citizen of Geneva with Rousseau, in the summer of 1762, when he was absorbed with religious or secular authorities in both France and Switzerland. On Palm Sunday, or 12 April, 1778, a few weeks away from death himself, he penned one of his most eloquent pages, the Tenth Walk of his Reveries, where he reflects that it was then fifty years to the day since he had first met Madame de Warens, with whom his destiny had been intertwined and in whose arms he had enjoyed a brief and tender period of his life in which he had been utterly himself, ‘without obstacle or mixed emotion and when [he] could truly say that [he] had lived’ (P i 1098–9; R 153). When in his late twenties Rousseau finally began to make his independent way in the world, he earned a modest livelihood mainly from private tuition and from the transcription of music, resolving to conquer Paris with a comic play, Narcissus, and a new system of musical notation. Soon after his arrival there in 1742 he was befriended by Rousseau Diderot, who was of similar age, background, and ambition and was to become his most intimate companion over the next fifteen years. The two men did not really possess the same temperament, with Diderot rather more urbane and affable, and Rousseau more sensitive and earnest, but they shared common interests in the theatre, the sciences, and especially music. On Diderot’s appointment with d’Alembert as joint editors of the Encyclopédie, Rousseau was commissioned to write most of the articles on musical subjects and another on political economy. In 1749, following the publication of his Letter on the Blind, Diderot suffered a brief period of detention in the prison of Vincennes, and Rousseau came to see him almost daily, imploring the authorities to release his companion. It was on his way there one day from his lodgings in Paris that he came across the notice of a prize essay competition on the subject of the arts and sciences and their moral impact on mankind, which was to alter the course of his life. Diderot at first shared Rousseau’s enthusiasm for the argument against civilization that forms the first Discourse, but only because he warmed to the provocative idea that a principal contributor to his dictionary of the arts and sciences should also undertake to discredit them. He was later to espouse radical moral ideas of his own, some of which were to bear a 6 striking resemblance to those of Rousseau himself, although he always remained convinced of what Rousseau had denied – that the progress of knowledge and culture leads to the improvement of human conduct and behaviour, whenever it springs from such genuine curiosity as is compatible with man’s nature. Rousseau’s stay in Paris had been interrupted briefly by his appointment in 1743–4 as Secretary to the French Ambassador in Venice. As a youth he had already visited Turin and learned Italian there, relishing Italian music, which he heard frequently, with an ardent enthusiasm for its spontaneity and directness that would never be tempered by any similar appreciation of the refinement of French musical textures. In accompanied the liturgy of the mass more appealing than the austere psalms that passed for music in the churches of Geneva, and in Venice he enthused as well over secular and vernacular music, which suffused his senses with popular tunes drawn from the streets and taverns no less than from the stage. Later, on his return to Paris, he was to contrast Italian opera favourably with that of France, on the grounds that the French language was less amenable to musical expression and that the French style of vocal music characteristically lacked a clear melodic line and was too much encumbered by superficial ornamentation and harmonic embellishments. His mid-century quarrel with Rameau, France’s leading composer and musical theorist of the day, was to turn on just such themes, and his Letter on French Music of 1753, for which he was to be hanged in effigy because its reflections on music were thought seditious, was to prove one of his most combustible works, and the only one which, as he claims in his Confessions (P i 384; C 358), ever put a halt to a political uprising in France. The monarchy’s expulsion of the magistrates of the Paris Parlement in November of that year, in a national crisis which also turned upon the conflict between Jansenists and Jesuits, had caused great turmoil, but not, he maintains, so much as had been stirred by his 7 The life and times of a citizen of Geneva Turin he had found the splendid orchestral performances which 3. Engraved title-page of Le Devin du village (Paris, 1753). work on music, which had averted a potential revolution against the state by turning it into a revolution against him. Paradoxically, the Letter on French Music proved to be his sole composition to win the almost universal endorsement of the philosophes, who took up the cause of Italian music with scarcely less enthusiasm. In 1752 Rousseau composed an opera, Le Devin du village or Village Soothsayer, which he produced in the Italian style and which came to be admired and even imitated, as well as surpassed in quality, by Gluck and Mozart. When he published his Dictionary of Music in 1767, largely developed from his articles for the Encyclopédie, he was to pursue his earlier ideas on music and opera in more detail than ever before, while in the Essay on the Origin of Languages, dating mainly from the early 1760s, he greater musical vitality to classical Latin over contemporary French, and more virtue and liberty to the citizens of ancient republics, who had, he suggests, expressed their fraternal feelings in open-textured song of a kind no longer prevalent among the modern subjects of monarchical rule. In his Confessions Rousseau remarks on his having also discovered, in Venice, that ‘Everything depends entirely upon politics’, and that therefore ‘a people is everywhere nothing but what its government makes of it’ (P i 404; C 377). Mankind was not naturally evil, he was convinced, but all too frequently became so under poor governments which generated vice. If everything depends upon politics then the upright character of his Genevan compatriots, on the one hand, and the moral corruption of a once-illustrious Venetian Republic, on the other, could both be traced to a similar source. Following his stay in Venice and his return to Paris, the capital of the greatest monarchy of the day, Rousseau was thus in a position to compare the contributions of three very distinct regimes, each having responsibility for shaping the character of its people. His first opportunity to draw together his ideas about the decline of culture and the political roots of vice arose in 1749, when he drafted his Discourse on the Arts and Sciences. While our 9 The life and times of a citizen of Geneva managed to join those ideas with his philosophy of history, ascribing forebears had been robust, the excess of luxury upon which enlightenment feeds has sapped us of our vitality and made us slaves to the trappings of culture, he contends there. Sparta had formed a durable nation so long as it was unadorned by the arts and sciences, but Athens, the most civilized state of antiquity, had been unable to arrest its decay into despotism, and the increasing grandeur of Rome and other empires had been accompanied by the decline of their military and political strength. Everywhere, Rousseau remarks, ‘the arts, letters, and sciences are spread like garlands of flowers round the iron chains by which [men] are weighed down’ (P iii 7; G 6). As much as any other theme in his later writings, this principle – in effect, that savoir springs from pouvoir – was henceforth to remain the cornerstone of his philosophy. Inspired by ancient Sophists and reformulated by Marx and Nietzsche, it was also to become a central tenet of the post-modernist Rousseau critique of the age of Enlightenment in general. This first of Rousseau’s two Discourses won the literary prize for which he entered it, and almost overnight the fuss it excited transformed him from an obscure man of letters approaching his middle age to the most celebrated scourge of modern civilization. One of the main factors underlying its notoriety was its manner of reversing a stock-in-trade eighteenth-century perspective of the epic struggle between virtue and vice. Voltaire spoke on behalf of many men of enlightened opinion in his day when, in his Philosophical Letters and elsewhere, he joined virtue to the advancement of learning and science and portrayed the progressive improvement of human conduct in the light of modern Europe’s slow awakening from dark centuries of superstition and ignorance. Diderot and d’Alembert conceived their Encyclopédie along much the same lines. Rousseau, by contrast, appeared to extol the merits of a barbarous golden age, from which mankind had fallen and lost grace because of an idolatrous lust for learning. Not only did he thus give the impression of favouring savagery over culture; to his enlightened contemporaries he seemed also to have forgotten that the principal source of misery and despair in the contemporary world, the Christian Church, drew its 10 power from much the same mysticism reinforced by ignorance which in the ancient world he applauded. Voltaire and his followers denounced this vision of our uncultivated innocence, and they accused Rousseau of having abandoned the causes of political and religious reform to which he ought to have subscribed in order to return instead to an uncouth state of stupidity. That assessment of his theory of man’s nature was in many ways wide of the mark, but it did place due weight upon one of the central tenets of his philosophy – which he often avowed to be the guiding thread of his works – that while our Creator had made everything good, all that had been forged by man was corrupt and depraved. Evil, Rousseau believed, was the characteristic outcome of human enterprise, if not always the object In the early 1750s he was absorbed mainly with his writings on music and with meeting the objections of some of the critics of his Discourse on the Arts and Sciences. To those who directed his attention away from the depravity of culture and towards the pernicious influence of political and economic factors instead, he owed a certain debt, since they reiterated the truth, as he saw it, of his Venetian discovery. By the autumn of 1753 he was to embark on a new and more subtle version of his philosophy of history, in which the pursuit of inequality rather than of luxury would be held responsible for our moral corruption, and in which he would take the relations of authority built round the institution of private property as the principal cause of humanity’s decline. The publicly authorized appropriation of the earth by some men at the expense of others must have led to the establishment of civil society through guile and injustice, Rousseau contends in his Discourse on Inequality of 1755, where he pursues that thesis in terms of a conjectural history of the human race, in which he also attempts to explain the social genesis of the family and of agriculture, and depicts the origins of different types of government in terms of the unequal distributions of private property that must have underpinned them. 11 The life and times of a citizen of Geneva of human design. In this hypothetical reconstruction of the past, he makes several observations of importance to his political and social theory which he had not articulated before. His fresh emphasis upon the institution of private property, rather than the pursuit of culture and learning, as the main source of our moral corruption was designed to challenge what Rousseau had come to understand as the foundations of modern jurisprudence from Grotius and Hobbes to Pufendorf and Locke. No other thinker of the Enlightenment was to confront that tradition so directly as Rousseau in his second Discourse, and no other eighteenth-century critique of earlier views of human nature was to offer such a dramatic conception of the evolutionary metamorphosis of our societal traits. Rousseau’s abstraction of primitive from civilized man in this work, moreover, came to be drawn around a dichotomy between our physical and moral attributes which he had not previously Rousseau addressed. Morality, he now insisted, did not stem from human nature but rather from the denaturation of man in society, with the striking inequalities that shaped our lives utterly different in kind from the insignificant natural variations between us. So far from expressing the best of what was latent in human nature, the establishment of private property, he argues in the Discourse on Inequality, had deformed it, turning the pursuit of honour and public esteem into an ignoble and dispiriting kind of competition. The hypothetical portrait of our original traits which he offers here for the first time actually drew savage man closer to other animals than to civilized man, giving Rousseau scope to speculate on zoological themes and on our differences from apes and other primates. Mankind, he had come to believe, was for better or worse the only species in the natural world which could make its own history, and the abuse of our capacities had ensured that in society we lived more anxious and miserable lives than all other creatures. The second Discourse was in time to exercise a profound influence upon the development of European thought in a variety of disciplines, but initially it had a less dramatic impact on its readers than his Discourse on the Arts and Sciences or his Letter on French Music. For the philosophes 12 with whom he had been previously allied, however, it confirmed and compounded their fears that his first Discourse was a statement of genuine belief and that he could no longer be regarded as an ally of enlightenment or progress. The need for him to part company with some of his former friends had certainly become apparent to Rousseau himself, who had always felt uneasy among atheists and sceptics. His unfashionable zeal, masked only by a certain timidity in public, had no doubt been inspired partly by Madame de Warens, and, in turn, it struck some of his Parisian friends, eventually Diderot himself, as evidence of insufferable self-righteousness and vanity. When he began to quarrel with his companions in the mid-1750s, he first he planned to return to Geneva but was dissuaded from that move mainly by Voltaire’s decision to settle there himself. Already twice imprisoned in the Bastille, Voltaire had merely sought a haven from which he might pursue his interests with less risk to his safety and in a milieu more congenial than the world of King Frederick the Great of Prussia, where bayonets had been preferred to books; but Rousseau perceived sinister motives in this encroachment of his native city. Voltaire would transform the simple manners of his compatriots into those of corrupt Parisians, he feared, so that in returning to his birthplace he would confront the same vices as had made him flee from France. He therefore decided instead to accept a country retreat called L’Ermitage, just north of Paris in the forest of Montmorency, offered to him by a friend of Diderot, Madame d’Épinay, who for a brief period was his benefactress and closest confidante, though she later proved the fiercest of all his adversaries who had known him well. With his arrival at L’Ermitage on 9 April 1756 began his disengagement from nearly all the philosophes with whom he had been allied since the early 1740s. He was soon to quarrel with Diderot, who had written a play in this period, The Natural Son, dealing in part with the evils of solitude, which he read as a personal gesture of contempt. When in 1756 Voltaire produced his poems on Natural Law and on the Lisbon earthquake of the previous 13 The life and times of a citizen of Geneva claimed that he could no longer tolerate their moral complacency. At year, in which he mocked the folly of blind faith in Providence that all was as it should be, Rousseau replied with his so-called ‘Letter on Providence’ that God was not responsible for evil and that the world of human suffering of which Voltaire complained had been manufactured only by man. Voltaire’s sarcastic response to Rousseau (as well as to Leibniz and Pope) was to take the form of a moral tale, which he entitled Candide. By 1758 Rousseau had effectively come to break off all relations with his former associates. A year earlier d’Alembert had produced a substantial article on Geneva for volume vii of the Encyclopédie, in which he put the case for the establishment of a theatre in that city, which would enhance its culture and thereby promote the moral sophistication of its citizens. Rousseau was convinced that Voltaire had conspired with Rousseau d’Alembert in writing this essay, and he conceived his Letter to d’Alembert on the Theatre as much to refute that usurper of his birthright as to confront d’Alembert himself. He decried the art of stagecraft as unsuited to the spirit of fraternal love which had once prevailed, and was now in need of restoration, in his native city. Just as Plato had 4. View of L’Ermitage engraved by Désiré after Gautier. 14 chosen to expel the captivating but factitious beauties of Homeric myth from his virtuous republic, so Rousseau, in his Letter to d’Alembert, attempted to preserve Geneva from the all-too-subtle irony of Molière, who could wonderfully transform pious integrity into hypocritical mischief through entertainments of gnarled subterfuge, making his compatriots rapt spectators of devious intent and thereby sap the nation of the unreflective and unmediated ardour of its own strength. It was also in the period immediately following his flight from Paris that Rousseau drafted his Julie, or The New Héloïse, the most popular work of fiction in late eighteenth-century France. This epistolary tale about the tribulations of frustrated love in its conflict with duty was partly inspired Rousseau’s most lyrical passages on romantic affection, tender sexuality, and rustic simplicity. If Candide was, in part, Voltaire’s fictional response to his ‘Letter on Providence’, then the preface to the New Héloïse may be regarded as the postscript to the Letter to d’Alembert which Rousseau had really meant to address to Voltaire. ‘Theatre is required in great cities’, Rousseau writes, ‘and a corrupt people needs its novels. I have witnessed the morals of my times and have published these letters. If only I could have lived in a century when I should have been obliged to throw them away!’ (P ii 5; J 3). In the same period, Rousseau completed his Emile, a work of almost equal length to The New Héloïse and which bears some relation to it, not least because it also concludes as a novel, although it begins as a treatise on education. The first book of the text opens with the statement of a principle which Rousseau had come by the mid-1750s to regard as the mainspring of his philosophy in general: ‘Everything is good when it springs from the hands of our Creator; everything degenerates when shaped by the hands of man’ (P iv 245; E 37). He conceived Emile’s central theme as a plan of education according to Nature rather than art, in which the impulses of the child are allowed to develop, each in its good time, rather than be forced, shaped 15 The life and times of a citizen of Geneva by the novels of Richardson and Prévost, and it contains some of 5. Henry Fuseli’s frontispiece to his own Remarks on the Writings and Conduct of J. J. Rousseau (London, 1767), depicting Rousseau pointing at Voltaire, astride humanity, with justice and liberty on the gibbet. prematurely, or subjected to exogenous control, by precept or instruction. Rousseau here maps out a genetic account of the spiritual growth of the individual along lines which reflect his evolutionary perspective, in the second Discourse, of our passage from a savage to a civilized state, albeit in Emile around images of sentiment and sexuality rather than of reason and authority. But in the blossoming of the child’s faculties, the rule that he must initally depend only on things and not upon men offers him the prospect of an education entirely distinct from that which must have led to the corruption of the human race in the past. Emile was the first of Rousseau’s works to point the way to a form of independence which might still be achieved by individuals even in corrupt society, from whose grip escape might now be contemplated, cautious, if unfulfilled, optimism about the prospects of humanity’s conceivable development which was not apparent in his earlier writings. No doubt this significant change of tone was partly inspired by Rousseau’s own success in emancipating himself from the trappings of Parisian society. According to his Confessions, however, the first work to which he turned in his new home was the Social Contract, a composition which he had already begun to plan while in Venice, and which he was now resolved to assemble into the finest of all his writings. The principles of the true social contract are perhaps best understood in contradiction with the sinister formula of agreement recounted in the second Discourse – such a contract, when properly construed, attaining rather than destroying the true liberty of citizens, by rendering them equal under law instead of subservient to their appointed political masters. Liberty and equality together are the two principles that ought to be the main objects of every system of legislation, Rousseau proclaims here, and much of the Social Contract is devoted to explaining why that should be so. Having already differentiated the moral and political from the natural and physical spheres of our lives, Rousseau contends that distinct forms of liberty or freedom are appropriate to each. Without government, he 17 The life and times of a citizen of Geneva by the cultivation of self-reliance. To that extent the work displays a argues, persons can be naturally free in the sense of not being subject to the will of others, but their freedom is attached merely to the satisfaction of their organic impulses. Only in political society, whose establishment requires that our natural liberty be abandoned, can we realize either civil or moral liberty, of which the first makes us dependent upon the whole community and the second obedient to laws that express our own collective will. In the Social Contract he claims that the state could serve as the instrument of freedom just if all its subjects were at the same time sovereign, for then alone can the people be truly said to rule themselves. Only when each of the state’s citizens takes direct part in legislation can they jointly check the abuse of power which some of them might seek to wield, he observes. While a number of his contemporaries, such as Montesquieu and Voltaire, had praised the liberal principles enshrined in the British Constitution, he instead, Rousseau on these grounds, judged the English system of parliamentary rule incompatible with the electorate’s freedom, in delegating the people’s sovereignty to their representatives. After the publication of his Social Contract, Rousseau drafted a Constitution for Corsica in 1765 and an essay on The Government of Poland around 1771, in both instances on the invitation of leading citizens of those fledgling regimes, who invited him to serve as their legislator. If Corsica had escaped invasion, and Poland its partitions, it might have been possible, in the late eighteenth century, to witness how the principles of the Social Contract could be applied to the constitutions of actual states. He had always intended that this should be the case, Rousseau claimed, in seeking the conjunction of political theory and practice, as much as his French Revolutionary admirers later, albeit in a different way. Contrasting his philosophy with that of Plato and also More, he maintained that he had not put forward an unworldly utopian ideal. On the contrary, his Social Contract had been intended to elucidate the theoretical foundations of an object close to home, in particular the constitution of Geneva, and it was just because that constitution had been forsaken, he believed, that he had incurred the wrath of the 18 current authorities of his native state (P iii 810). This was one of the main arguments of his third major work devoted largely to politics, his Letters from the Mountain of 1764. The feature of his Social Contract which, in his lifetime, aroused the deepest public fury, however, was its penultimate chapter on the civil religion. Rousseau there stresses the significance of a religious as well as political foundation for our civic responsibilities, according to which citizens perform and love their duty as a matter of patriotic faith, joining them together in common devotion to an almighty, benign, and tolerant Divinity. That aspect of his thought, partly inspired by his beloved Machiavelli, brought Rousseau into conflict both with the leading critics. To philosophes intent upon reforming the ancien régime, his religious zealotry seemed yet again a betrayal of the Enlightenment and a dark reinvocation of blind faith in a dawning age of reason. On the other hand, his express condemnation of Christianity, which he described as best suited to tyrannical government, outraged the Church and political authorities alike. His ‘Profession of Faith of the Savoyard Vicar’ in Emile, moreover, published at almost the same time as the Social Contract, set forth the fullest and most eloquent statement of his philosophy of natural as opposed to revealed religion, which dismayed those authorities even more. From their censure, Rousseau was never really to recover. Both Emile and the Social Contract were banned or confiscated in Paris and burned in Geneva. Forced to flee from the one city and subject to arrest in the other, he found himself in 1762 a fugitive from justice, surprised both at the vehemence of the official reaction to claims which he thought would be attributed to truly Christian scruples in contrast with the atheism of so many philosophes, and at the initial failure of his compatriots to come to his aid. In May 1763, in despair, having found temporary refuge in Môtiers, near Neuchâtel, under the nominal jurisdiction of Frederick the Great of Prussia, he repudiated his Genevan 19 The life and times of a citizen of Geneva religious and political establishment of his day and with many of its Rousseau 6. Portrait of Rousseau attributed to Greuze. citizenship. Thereafter he remained homeless, often obliged to travel incognito, at the mercy of protectors whose real aim, he sometimes suspected, was to ensnare and malign him. One such protector was to be David Hume, who in January 1766 personally accompanied Rousseau to England, where he stayed almost eighteen months, principally at Wootton, in Staffordshire – in that time, overwhelmed by suspicions of an international conspiracy to discredit his character, managing to bring great misery upon himself, and much discomfort to Hume. Real persecution compounded the paranoia with which he was undoubtedly afflicted at least from the mid-1760s, and for the rest of his life he was convinced that his former companions in the vanguard of the 20 Enlightenment – Diderot, d’Alembert, d’Holbach, and Grimm – assisted by Voltaire and his patrician friends, who had always loathed him, were in league with his political enemies in a monumental network of conspiracy against him. Having returned to France on an undertaking to desist from publishing his writings, he found respite only in solitude, the study of botany, and a romantically lyrical communion with Nature, as recounted in his last major work, for some readers his greatest masterpiece, the Reveries, which would appear posthumously with the first part of his Confessions. In 1778, soon after being drawn yet again to a refuge just north of Paris, at Ermenonville, provided by the Marquis de Girardin, he died of apoplexy, ‘without uttering a single word’, his widow reports (L 8344), contradicting groundless suggestions that he Yet while Rousseau had become estranged from mainstream Enlightenment thinkers, he had a great many passionate followers as well, throughout France and among radical circles in Geneva and above all, perhaps, in enlightened Europe’s peripheries – Italy, Scotland, and Germany, where Kant and Goethe were to prove the most prominent of his admirers of the next generation or two. In the course of the French Revolution, especially, when the manuscript of his Confessions was presented to the Convention and his body was ceremoniously transported to Paris, his influence upon eighteenth-century life and thought was at its zenith. No other figure of his age had more clearly expressed the Revolutionaries’ commitment to the principles of liberty, equality, and fraternity, nor a deeper devotion to the ideal of popular sovereignty, whose adoption in France signalled an end to the ancien régime. In the political career of the Incorruptible Robespierre in particular – his opposition to patronage and to priestly theology, his patriotism and promotion of the Cult of the Supreme Being – can be found, as well as much else besides, the most zealous practical exposition of Rousseau’s doctrines. Rousseau himself never advocated revolution, judged political uprisings worse than the disease they were intended to cure, and held little hope for the political salvation of 21 The life and times of a citizen of Geneva had committed suicide. mankind. But he foresaw Europe’s impending crisis and the advent of a revolutionary age, hoping it might be averted. When the French Revolution was launched a decade after his death, many of its leaders nevertheless drew up their programmes and constitutions in the fiery light of his philosophy. Because of that connection, he would come to be decried as the most villainous thinker of the whole of the eighteenth century when the Revolution soured and gave birth, first to the Jacobin Terror, then to Bonapartism, and, according to his critics, eventually to Rousseau modern totalitarianism in general. 22 Chapter 2 Culture, music, and the corruption of morals Rousseau remarks in his Confessions that he had been thunderstruck on reading the notice of the Academy of Dijon in the Mercure de France of October 1749, heralding a competition for the best essay on the question ‘Has the rebirth of the arts and sciences contributed to the purification of morals?’. ‘The moment I read this announcement I saw another universe and became a different man’, he writes (P i 351; C 327). He had stopped by a tree to catch his breath, moved almost to delirium by a fiery vision of the natural goodness of humanity and the evil contradictions of our social order, which had kindled in his mind most of the leading ideas of what would become his principal works, even though he was never to recapture more than its faint shadow. Yet while the Discourse on the Arts and Sciences forms the most immediate expression of that vision, Rousseau eventually came to regard it as among the worst of his major writings. The text which launched his literary career had neither order, nor logic, nor structure, he lamented, and, though it was full of warmth and vigour, it was, on his own testimony, the feeblest and least elegant of his celebrated works (P i 352; C 328–9). It is also, as was soon to be noted by his detractors, the least original. Its central theme is that civilization has been the bane of humanity and that the perfection of our arts and sciences has been accompanied by the corruption of our morals. Before we acquired the skills and 23 attributes of cultured men, and before our patterns of life came to be moulded by false values and factitious needs, our manners were ‘rustic but natural’. With the birth and dissemination of knowledge, however, our original purity became progressively debased by sophistical taste and custom, by the ‘perfidious veil of politeness’, and by ‘all those vicious ornaments’ of fashion, until our pristine virtue had disappeared as if carried away by an ebbing tide (P iii 8, 10, 21; G 7–9, 20). We cannot but regret our loss of the simplicity of that earliest epoch when our forebears had lived together in huts and sought little more than the approval of their gods, Rousseau maintains. In the beginning the world’s only adornments would have been sculpted by Nature herself, and thereafter it has been those civilizations which remain closest to Her, least burdened by the trappings of culture and learning, which have proved the most vigorous and robust. Our arts and sciences, he Rousseau observes, do not inspire individuals with courage or the spirit of patriotism; on the contrary they sap men of both their devotion to the state and their strength to preserve it from invasion. Since the marvellous inventions of the Chinese failed to ward off their subjection to the coarse and ignorant Tartars, the erudition of their sages was manifestly useless. On the other hand, the Persians, who mastered virtue rather than science, were easily able to conquer Asia, while the greatness of the German and Scythian nations was firmly grounded on the simplicity, innocence, and patriotic spirit of their inhabitants (P iii 11, 22; G 10–11, 20). Above all, the history of Sparta, when contrasted with that of Athens, demonstrates how much more durable and resistant to the vices of tyranny are those communities which have been spared the vain monuments of culture. Socrates, the wisest person in Athens, cautioned his fellow citizens of the dangerous consequences of their arrogance, and later, at Rome, Cato followed his example and inveighed against the venomously seductive delights of art and ostentation that undermined the vitality of his compatriots. Yet each man’s warnings went unheeded, and an entirely specious form of learning came to prevail in both Athens 24 and Rome, to the detriment of military discipline, agricultural production, and political vigilance. The Roman Republic, in particular, once the temple of virtue, soon became the decadent theatre of crime, slowly succumbing under the yoke with which it had earlier harnessed its barbarian captives. Much the same pattern of decline had also marked the collapse of the ancient empires of Egypt, Greece, and Constantinople, Rousseau adds, proclaiming it a general rule that great civilizations decay under the weight of their scientific and artistic progress (P iii 10–14; G 9–13). The first Discourse offers little explanation of these developments, however, barely sketching the way the arts and sciences could have On the one hand, all our sciences, Rousseau suggests, have been formed out of idleness, each discipline stemming from the vices to which indolence gives rise – astronomy from superstition, for instance, geometry from avarice, and physics from excessive curiosity. On the other hand, our arts are everywhere nourished by luxury, which is itself born out of sloth and the vanity of men. Luxury is presented as a crucial feature, since Rousseau maintains that it can seldom thrive in the absence of the arts and sciences, while they never exist without it. According to his argument, it seems that the dissolution of morals must have been a necessary consequence of luxury, which, in turn, stemmed from idleness, with the human corruption and enslavement that have been such characteristic features of the history of all civilizations presented as appropriate punishment for our swollen endeavour to advance beyond that state of happy ignorance in which it would have been a blessing to remain forever (P iii 15, 17–19, 21; G 14, 16–17, 20). In all these respects, the Discourse on the Arts and Sciences comprises the first major statement of the philosophy of history – to the effect that our apparent cultural and social progress has led only to our real moral degradation – which Rousseau was to develop as one of the most central themes of his works. But in the first Discourse that philosophy of 25 Culture, music, and the corruption of morals been so comprehensively responsible for the moral decadence of man. Rousseau 7. Frontispiece and title-page of the Discours sur les sciences et les arts (1750). history still appears rudimentary and obscure, comprised, as it is there, of at least three distinct theses about the course and circumstances of our corruption: first, the suggestion that mankind has declined progressively from the innocence of its earliest primitive state; second, the claim that nations which are artistically and scientifically underdeveloped are morally superior to their sophisticated counterparts; and third, the contention that great civilizations have become decadent under the weight of their own cultural progress. To his readers, these propositions seemed not to accord easily with one another, especially since the tribute Rousseau pays to the mode of life of primitive man, on the one hand, and to robust civilization which succeeds savage society, on the other, is compounded by his further proposition – so fashionable in the Enlightenment – that human history had been interrupted by a reversion, under several centuries of medieval barbarism and superstition, to a state worse than that of our original ignorance. At the end of his text Rousseau even launches upon an entirely new thesis to the effect that it is not really the arts and sciences 26 as such but rather their abuse by persons of ordinary talent which has been the true source of our misfortunes, and he actually concludes his work with the observation that great scientists and artists should be entrusted with the task of building monuments to honour the glory of the human spirit. The rest of us lesser mortals, he exclaims, should aspire to no more than the obscurity and mediocrity to which we have been destined. It is difficult to grasp why Rousseau thought such sentiments appropriate to a critique of the arts and sciences and a defence of the virtues of ignorance, innocence, and common humanity (P iii 6, 22, 29–30; G 6, 20, 27–8). Nor was he clear as to the precise nature of the contribution which he appeared to be quite simply that the progress of the arts and sciences has been responsible for the debasement of morals, but he also supposed that the arts and sciences were nourished by the indolence, vanity, and luxury to which men aspire and which some enjoy. Had the advancement of culture been the cause of our corruption, then, or its effect? Rousseau, whose main concern in the work is to portray the evils which invariably derive from the pursuit of culture and knowledge, but who equally proclaims that our arts and sciences owe their origin to our vices (P iii 17, 19; G 16, 18), seems to have been unable to make up his mind. One of the reasons for his irresolution may be the fact that so many features of his argument were borrowed from earlier thinkers, such as Montesquieu, Fénelon, Montaigne, Seneca, Plato, and, above all, Plutarch, whose writings he had read at length, and whose commentaries on the superiority of nature over artifice, or the oppressiveness of inequality, or the decadence of civilization, were so much endorsed or recapitulated in his text. In his Essay on the Reigns of Claudius and Nero Diderot later remarked that ‘a hundred apologies for ignorance in the face of the arts’ and sciences’ advance had been made before Rousseau’, and he was certainly correct. But the first Discourse 27 Culture, music, and the corruption of morals believed the growth of culture had made to our decline. His thesis 8. Portrait of Diderot by Van Loo. lacks originality not only because it bears the general influence of other works in a similar vein to which Rousseau turned for guidance, or because his scholarship is plainly second-hand – his account of the Scythians, for instance, drawn essentially from Horace, his description of the Germans from Tacitus, his sketch of the Persians from Montaigne, and his contrast between Sparta and Athens from several writers, but most especially Bossuet and the historian Charles Rollin. Its derivative character is due above all to the fact that the very words Rousseau employs to express his principal ideas were often borrowed from his authorities. Apart from the numerous references whose sources are manifestly Sciences drawn, without acknowledgement, from Montesquieu’s Spirit of the Laws and one unattributed transcription from Bossuet’s Discourse on Universal History; there are several snatches from Plutarch’s Lives and upwards of fifteen extracts from the Essays of Montaigne, only a few of which allude to their source; while the very last line of Rousseau’s text is adapted from both Plutarch and Montaigne together. Dom Joseph Cajot’s Plagiarisms of Rousseau, published in 1766, may have been excessively severe – and in most instances incorrect – in its imputations, but it remains the case that the Discourse on the Arts and Sciences is the only one of Rousseau’s writings which invites such suspicions. Despite the polemical tone and character of the argument, it is directed against no other work in particular, and Rousseau appears to have turned to his sources more in order to recapitulate them than to lend weight to his own ideas. The difference between his first and second Discourse with regard to this point could hardly be more stark, since in the Discourse on Inequality he was to embark on a refutation of most of the figures mentioned in his text, whereas in the Discourse on the Arts and Sciences he managed little more than to reflect, albeit perhaps in a more powerful idiom of his own, the disparate views already advanced by its precursors. His first major work enunciates a philosophy of history to which he was to adhere for the rest of his life and which his 29 Culture, music, and the corruption of morals clear, there is at least one passage in the Discourse on the Arts and contemporaries, at least, came to recognize as his most central doctrine. It was the first of his writings emblazoned with his signature ‘Citizen of Geneva’, thereby proclaiming his proud identity and authorship. Yet in launching his literary career, it was to prove his least characteristic, least personal, achievement. Rousseau’s development as a writer, nevertheless, owed much to the dispute which exploded around his Discourse on the Arts and Sciences immediately following its publication and which raged for at least three years thereafter. In the course of that controversy, by way of attempting to vindicate his work against his critics, he came to assemble, elaborate, and refine his original claims in a manner that was often different from their first formulation. He made no effort to reply to all his detractors, but he tried to rebut at least six works in particular that came to his Rousseau notice. Several of his critics charged that he had failed to specify the precise point of our moral decline, so that he had given the impression of preferring Europe’s centuries of barbarism to the renaissance of the sciences which followed, and a few decried his general lack of scholarship, in his misunderstanding of the brutal nature of the ancient Scythians, or his neglect of the fact that some of the figures he had praised, such as Seneca, believed that virtue was enhanced and not debased by literature. To these allegations Rousseau retorted, particularly in a ‘Letter to the abbé Raynal’, that his aim had been to put forward a general thesis about the connection between artistic and scientific advance, on the one hand, and moral decadence, on the other, rather than to trace the course of any particular set of events, so that such critics had misunderstood the purpose of his work (P iii 31–2; G 29–30). He was to pursue this theme of generality much further in his Discourse on Inequality, where he shifts his attention from the untainted civilizations of the ancient world to the nature of primeval man and to a condition of humanity so remote that no historical research could possibly uncover its true features. After the publication 30 of his first Discourse, Rousseau was to become progressively more concerned with the ultimate sources of our decadence and less with its particular manifestations in different cultures. Paradoxically, however, while he gradually set his sights upon our most distant past, his evidence came to be drawn from an increasingly contemporary world, in effect populated by savages who had thus far escaped the miseries of human history rather than by the heroes and sages of antiquity. By the mid-1750s, that is, his fidelity to the venerable Lives of Plutarch came at least to be counterbalanced by a new enthusiasm for the General History of Voyages, edited by the author of Manon Lescaut, the abbé Prévost. As the divisions between man’s nature and culture which Rousseau perceived grew sharper and bolder, so too did the course of the development of his early social theory the deficiencies of his historical scholarship were soon to be overcome by the breadth and sweep of his speculative insights into the general plight of our species as a whole. Several of the critics of his first Discourse also accused him of resuscitating the nostalgic chimera of an ancient golden age, which had existed in myth and poetry but never in fact. To this objection Rousseau replied, especially in his answer to Borde’s Discourse on the Advantages of the Arts and Sciences of 1751, that the idea of an ancient golden age was not a historical illusion but a philosophical abstraction, no more chimerical in substance, and no less necessary for our self-understanding and well-being, than the concept of virtue itself (P iii 80; G 71). He had not juxtaposed past and present epochs of our history in order to encourage the rescue of fictitious virtues or the lost innocence of antiquity. In two of his works stemming from the first Discourse, the ‘Observations’ addressed to King Stanislaw of Poland and the preface to his play Narcissus, he observes that a people, once it was corrupted, could never return to a virtuous state, and this was a thesis to which he was to subscribe throughout his life. Above all, he took great offence at the suggestion, first made by the 31 Culture, music, and the corruption of morals arguments he put forward to portray these differences, and in the mathematician and historian Joseph Gautier, that he had become an apologist of ignorance who appeared to believe that our culture should be crushed and our libraries burned. Of course we must not plunge Europe back into a state of barbarism, he responded, nor was he advocating the obliteration of our libraries, academies, or universities, least of all the destruction of society itself (P ii 971–2; P iii 55–6, 95; G 50–1, 84–5, 103). Reversion to a natural state is no more possible for civilized man than would be the recovery of innocence or ignorance of vice. Following such objections to his Discourse on the Arts and Sciences, Rousseau was always to stress that the morally upright citizen must attempt to make his way in this world rather than in some ancient paradise of remote imagination. The alternative course of solitude and communion with Nature which he would personally espouse towards the end of his life was not one he was to Rousseau recommend as a strategy for disenchanted subjects of modern states, and he remained adamant that his ideas were neither utopian nor violent in their implications. He was impressed by the force of some of the objections raised by his critics, and occasionally modified or abandoned certain features of his theory in the light of them. Thus when King Stanislaw challenged his account of the connection between virtue and ignorance, on the grounds that uncultured men whom Rousseau had applauded were sometimes brutal rather than benign, he accepted the point and proposed a distinction between two forms of ignorance, of which one was odious and terrible, and the other modest and pure (P iii 53–4; G 48–9). Yet without further elaboration this reply was hardly convincing, and in his later writings he was to prove more hesitant in ascribing the moral innocence of primitive men to their mere lack of learning. The philosopher Charles Borde, whom Rousseau had befriended in the early 1740s, claimed that the author of the Discourse on the Arts and Sciences had also been unwise to praise the military prowess of uncivilized peoples, whose barbarous conquests had been evidence of their injustice rather than innocence. Rousseau was quick to 32 concur, allowing that it is not our natural destiny to destroy one another. Although he at first suggests that devotion to war for the sake of conquest is unlike willingness to fight for the defence of liberty (P iii 82; G 72), he was never again to portray the ideal of military valour in quite the shining colours he had employed in the first Discourse. He did not abandon his belief, inspired by Machiavelli, that the liberties of the Roman Republic had been sustained by its citizens’ militia, but in the Discourse on Inequality and afterwards he was to portray all wars as criminal, murderous, execrable, and – for the combatants themselves – pointless. While Rousseau thus made a few concessions to his critics, he turned This is particularly true of his replies to the claims of Stanislaw and Borde that the moral degradation of man was attributable to an excess of wealth rather than learning, and of his response to Borde’s contention that the decline of nations could ultimately be due only to political causes. In his ‘Observations’ he acknowledges that diverse customs, climate, laws, economies, and governments (to which d’Alembert had drawn attention in objecting to Rousseau’s thesis in his ‘Preliminary Discourse’ to the Encyclopédie of 1751) must all have figured in the formation of peoples’ moral traits (P iii 42–3; G 39), and thereafter he was to address the impact of such factors more directly. In his ‘Last Reply’ to Borde of 1752, for instance, he notes that luxury, which he had earlier condemned as the principal cause of our decadence, was itself due largely to the decline of agriculture in the modern world (P iii 79; G 70). In the same text, and subsequently in his preface to Narcissus, he draws attention for the first time in his writings to the nefarious influence of private property. In the ‘Last Reply’ he deals mainly with the concept of ownership, and with the brutal division of the earth between masters and slaves which the practical application of that concept entails, largely in order to challenge Borde’s thesis that men in their most primitive state must already have been fierce and aggressive. ‘Before those dreadful words thine and mine were invented’, he exclaims, ‘before there were 33 Culture, music, and the corruption of morals other charges to more productive use in the development of his theory. men so abominable as to crave for superfluities while others starve of hunger’, I should like to know just what our ancestors’ vices could have been (P iii 80; G 71). In the preface to Narcissus he concentrates instead upon the fact that the moral attributes of the savage were markedly superior to those of the European, because savages were unscathed by the habitual vices of greed, envy, and deception which in the civilized world have caused men to scorn and make enemies of one another. ‘The word property’, he reflects there, ‘has almost no meaning among savages’. ‘They have no conflicting interests around it; nothing drives them to deceive each other’, as covetous civilized men always do (P ii 969–70 n; G 101 n). In these two passages directed against the critics of his Discourse on the Arts and Sciences, we thus find Rousseau’s earliest major statements of the thesis which he was later to expound in the form of a challenge – on that occasion to Locke’s theory of property – in Rousseau the Discourse on Inequality. Rousseau was now beginning to look more closely at the role of political factors as well. The evils of contemporary society had been described before by many figures, he reflects in the preface to Narcissus, but while others had perceived the problem, he had actually uncovered its causes, and the essential truth he had learned by 1753 was that all our vices stem ultimately not from our nature but from the ways in which we have been badly governed (P ii 969; G 101). He was to make the same point again two years later in his Discourse on Political Economy, where he remarks that ‘Peoples are in the long run what their governments make of them’ (P iii 251; S 13). He was to stress it once more in the following decade in his Letter to Christophe de Beaumont, where he proclaims that the counterfeit behaviour of civilized men is caused by our ‘social order’, which brings continual tyranny to bear upon our nature (P iv 966). And around 1770 he was to reflect in his Confessions that the truth of this principle had already been apparent to him thirty years earlier, during his sojourn in Venice, when he had witnessed the dire consequences for its people which followed from the defects of that nation’s government. The preface to Narcissus thus embraces the first statement of an idea 34 whose elaboration in several contexts and in different forms was to occupy a major part of Rousseau’s life and works. With regard to the contribution made by wealth and riches to our moral decline, Rousseau soon showed himself to be only partly in accord with the ideas of Stanislaw and Borde. In several fragmentary writings of the early 1750s, especially a short piece on ‘Luxury, Commerce, and the Arts’, he acknowledges that the cupidity of man is a manifestation of his desire to set himself above his neighbours, so that the introduction of gold in human affairs had been unavoidably accompanied by the inequality of its distribution, from which there then issued the vice of poverty and the humiliation of the poor by the rich (P iii 522). But even mankind’s moral corruption, he insists that it was not the principal cause of our decline. On the contrary, as he declares in his ‘Observations’, wealth and poverty are relative terms which reflect rather than determine the extent of inequality in society. Rearranging the genealogy of vices which he had portrayed in the first Discourse, he now proposes that pride of place in the dismal order of our corruption should be granted to inequality, which was then followed by wealth, which in turn made possible the growth of luxury and indolence, which then gave rise to the arts, on the one hand, and to the sciences, on the other (P iii 49–50; G 45). Here was a new version of his argument, placing the arts and sciences last, and not first, as his critics supposed. At least part of the reason for this modification of his views may be gleaned from his ‘Observations’ and the preface to Narcissus, where he suggests that while the progress of culture has been responsible for a whole train of vices, it is fundamentally our desire to shine through learning rather than the achievement of learned men which undermines our morals in civilized society. For our pursuit of culture above all else expresses our resolve to distinguish ourselves from our neighbours and compatriots, he claims, in both places elaborating a brief remark about 35 Culture, music, and the corruption of morals in recognizing the part played by the accumulation of riches in ‘the rage for distinction’ that figures in the first Discourse itself, recollecting perhaps the main thrust of Fénelon’s most central contribution to the quarrel of the ancients and moderns which had fermented in France for more than thirty years around the turn of the eighteenth century. It is not so much our devotion to excellence as our wish to command the respect of others that has prompted us to manufacture the artefacts and instruments of advanced societies, so that civilization seems only a fulfilment of our attempts to establish an unequal distribution of public esteem (P ii 965; P iii 19, 48; G 18, 43–4, 97). Moral virtue cannot truly exist, Rousseau contends, unless individual shares of talent are roughly equal. The only safeguard we had ever had against corruption, he remarks in his ‘Observations’, was that original equality, now irredeemably lost, which had once conserved our innocence and been the true source of virtue (P iii 56; G 50–1). Thus Rousseau does he conclude that our craving for distinction in the arts and sciences is a manifestation of much the same factitious feeling as the desire to dominate in politics – a sentiment upon which he would soon focus his attention in the Discourse on Inequality. In all these respects, therefore, Rousseau’s replies to the critics of his Discourse on the Arts and Sciences led him towards the more political, social, and economic lines of argument that he was to pursue in the second Discourse and beyond. Yet he never abandoned his earlier views about the importance of the arts and sciences as causal agents of human corruption. On the contrary, throughout the dispute surrounding his Discourse on the Arts and Sciences, he consistently reaffirms the claims which he had made in his prize essay about the interconnections between vanity, sloth, luxury, and culture, even while extending his argument to accommodate other factors. One of his critics, Claude-Nicolas Le Cat, a professor of anatomy and surgery and Permanent Secretary of the Academy of Rouen, managed to provide Rousseau with a whole new front for the development of his ideas, in challenging him to be more precise as to which areas of culture were subject to his imputations. Surely Rousseau did not propose to include 36 music among those arts and sciences which had brought about our degradation, Le Cat exclaimed, confident that the Encyclopédie’s principal contributor on musical subjects must know better than anyone else how useful and advantageous this art has been, and how, at the very least, it must form an exception to his general thesis. Le Cat’s supposition could scarcely have been further from the truth. In 1753, at the height of the Querelle des Bouffons, the controversy surrounding Pergolesi’s Serva padrona and Italian opera buffa which divided the patrons of the Paris Opéra and the French court into musical factions, Rousseau produced his Letter on French Music, which provoked an even greater storm of protest than the Discourse on the Arts and are more appropriate to music than others, on account of their more mellifluous vowels, their more gentle inflections, and their more precisely measured figures of speech. Such languages, above all Italian in particular, he claims, lend themselves to clear melodic intonations and to expression in song. Other languages, like French, are marked by a lack of sonorous vowels and by consonants so coarse that agreeable tunes cannot be sung in them, leaving composers from nations with such a speech impediment obliged to embellish their music with the strident noise of harmonic accompaniment. Articulation of the French language in unadorned song is thus impossible, and if the people of France should ever seek a form of music of their own, he concludes in the last line of his text, so much the worse for them. Following this provocative work and these defamatory remarks, Rousseau was widely denounced for his affront to public taste. If his Letter on French Music did not quite excite an insurrection, it made him appear, for the first time in his life, an enemy of the French state. As Voltaire was later to recognize, Rousseau is nowhere so politically inflammatory as when commenting on music. If Le Cat had been able to read the section devoted to that subject which Rousseau originally drafted as a part of the Discourse on 37 Culture, music, and the corruption of morals Sciences three years earlier. Some languages, Rousseau contends there, Rousseau 9. Title-page of the second edition of the Lettre sur la musique française (Paris, 1753). Inequality, and which eventually appeared posthumously in 1781 as two chapters of the Essay on the Origin of Languages, he would have understood why music could form no exception to Rousseau’s general thesis of the Discourse on the Arts and Sciences. On the contrary, the corruption of human morality was most clearly manifested, according to Rousseau, in the history of the development of music. Our first languages, he contends in the Essay, probably arose in the southern regions of the world, where the climate was mild and the land fertile. They must have had a rhythmic and melodic character and would have been poetic rather than prose, sung rather than spoken, so that in their first articulations of impulsive passions our forebears must, in short, have been enchanting (P v 407, 410–11, 416; G 278, 282, 287). But languages which would subsequently have arisen in the inclement 38 conditions of the north would have first expressed men’s needs rather than their passions and would have been less sonorous and more shrill (P v 380, 407–9; G 253, 279–81). With the eventual conquest of the Mediterranean world under a wave of barbarian invasions, the guttural and staccato speech of northern men must have taken precedence over the mellifluous intonations which had served for the expression of human sentiments before, and all the sweetness, measure, and grace of our original languages would have been lost (P v 425–7; G 296–8). The melodic forms of diction would have been suppressed, claims Rousseau, and our utterances would have been progressively deprived of their initial charm. Under the bondage of barbarian rule and agricultural labour, humdrum prose would in effect have taken languages, particularly the earliest forms of French, English, and German, accordingly would have become prosaic (P v 392, 409; G 265, 280–1). Music, on the other hand, would have been rendered senseless by the loss of its semantic component when appropriated by the languages of prose, and it would have come to be developed further only by the Gothic innovation of harmony, implanting chordal patterns upon the utterances of men that yielded artificial pleasures in place of the natural delights of vernacular song. Under these pressures music would have become more instrumental than vocal; and the calculation of intervals would have been substituted for the finesse of melodic inflections (P v 424; G 295). Prose would have come to be refined in writing rather than speech, communicated no longer with expressive force but only the exactitude of grammatical rules and a precise dictionary of terms, which it would have been necessary to consult in order to ascertain one’s feelings (P v 386, 415; G 258, 286). As if to meet Le Cat’s challenge to his philosophy of history, Rousseau entitled the final chapter of his essay ‘The Relation of Languages to Government’ and proclaims there that languages which have come to 39 Culture, music, and the corruption of morals precedence over poetic song, and with the emergence of prose, be separated from music are inimical to freedom. A prosaic rhetoric inspires servile manners, and speech made hollow by its lack of tone and rhythm, he asserts, also makes for hollow men. The languages of modern Europe have become suitable only for discourse at close quarters, as the ineffectual chatter of persons who just murmur feebly to one another with voices which lack inflection, and therefore spirit and passion as well. As our speech has succumbed to the loss of its musical traits it has been deprived of its original vigour and clarity and become little more than the faint mutterings of individuals who have no strength of character or purpose. And if this is the private aspect of our contemporary languages, their public manifestation, according to Rousseau, is more oppressive still. For men who govern others but have nothing to say themselves can do little else when the people are assembled apart from shout and preach to them, in intemperate and Rousseau unintelligible pronouncements. The proclamations of our rulers and the supplications of our priests continually abuse our sensibilities and make us numb, and tortuous harangues and sermons, delivered by both secular and religious charlatans, have become the sole form of popular oratory in the modern world (P v 428–9; G 299). Both the private and public faces of language, Rousseau concludes, thus provide an accurate portrait of the utterly degraded state into which our societies have fallen. Conversation has become covert, political discourse has become barren, and we have all succeeded in bringing our original manner of speaking up to date only by becoming the speechless auditors of those who rule by diatribes and recitations from the pulpit. In fact since even these perverted forms of rhetoric are no longer necessary to keep us in our allotted places, the rulers of modern states have correctly come to understand that they can maintain their authority without convening any popular meetings or assemblies at all. They have only to direct the attention of their subjects to the many things which they might exchange with each other and away from the few thoughts that they might still wish to communicate, so that in their latest form the vocal intonations which had once expressed our 40 pleasures have been reconstituted as the terms that denote our trades. Whereas the words aimez-moi must in the past have been superseded by aidez-moi, now all that we say to each other is donnez de l’argent (P v 408, 428; G 279, 298–9). In Book iii, chapter 15 of the Social Contract Rousseau would later pursue much the same argument, shorn of its musical but not its political dimension. Of course the Essay on the Origin of Languages must have been inspired by much more besides Le Cat’s objection to the Discourse on the Arts and Sciences. On Rousseau’s own testimony it originally formed a section of the Discourse on Inequality, which he withdrew because it was too long and out of place, and which in 1755 he then appended to a study of the criticisms of his articles on music for the Encyclopédie, only to withdraw it once again. The Essay’s stress upon the priority of melody over harmony in music is central to the case developed by Rousseau against Rameau, who throughout his life had insisted upon the supremacy of harmony, which he explained in the light of his innovative notion of the fundamental bass of a resonating body. But Rousseau’s treatment of music and language in the Essay forms an intrinsic part of his philosophy of history as well, and it comprises a more richly drawn illustration of his claim that the progress of civilization has led to the corruption of morals than can be found in his discussion of any of the other arts or sciences. To that extent it takes up Le Cat’s challenge to his original thesis most directly. In a note of his ‘Last Reply’ to Borde, Rousseau claims that he had foreseen and dealt in advance with all his detractors’ plausible complaints against his case (P iii 71–2; G 64), but he thereby does scant justice to their ingenuity or to the subtlety of his own rejoinders, whose fresh themes are largely imperceptible in his original text. At least one objection to the first Discourse, however, was to remain unanswered in Rousseau’s early writings. An anonymous critic – possibly the abbé Raynal, who was later to collaborate with Diderot and others in compiling a massive History of the Two Indies – complained that 41 Culture, music, and the corruption of morals Principle of Melody that he had drafted partly in reply to Rameau’s Rousseau 10. Manuscript title-page of Du principe de la mélodie. Rousseau had failed to offer any practical conclusions following from his thesis and had neglected to propose a remedy for the condition he described. In his ‘Last Reply’ to Borde, Rousseau acknowledges the force of this criticism and remarks only that he had seen the evil and had tried to locate its sources. The search for a remedy, he claims at this stage of his life, was a task he must leave to others (P iii 95; G 85). He did not take up the challenge in his Discourse on Inequality nor anywhere else in his writings of the early and mid-1750s, but neither did he abandon it completely. In certain works of that period or soon afterwards which 42 were not destined for publication, he could permit his imagination to soar in political reverie which might appear to counsel radical change, as in the second chapter of Book i of his Manuscrit de Genève, an early version of the Social Contract embracing his response to some remarks of Diderot in the Encyclopédie, where he calls for the establishment of ‘new associations to correct . . . the defect of society in general’ (P iii 288; S 159). Subsequently in his Letter to d’Alembert, and in the final version of his Social Contract, by way of attempting to breathe fresh life into ideals of civil association that mankind had lost, he was to propose a set of principles according to which our moral sentiments might be uplifted rather than debased, only to find the authorities of his native Geneva and adopted France so alarmed as to regard even his presence 43 Culture, music, and the corruption of morals among them a threat to public order. Chapter 3 Human nature and civil society The Discourse on the Origins of Inequality is the most important and substantial of Rousseau’s early writings, and with the Social Contract and Emile it has come to exercise the widest influence of all his works. Yet its impact on its readers was not so immediate or tempestuous as the public response which had greeted his Discourse on the Arts and Sciences or his Letter on French Music, since unlike the first Discourse it failed to win the prize of the Academy of Dijon for which it had been entered in a fresh competition, and it lacked the topicality of Rousseau’s contribution to the Querelle des Bouffons, which had stirred strong feelings among partisans of French and Italian music and politics alike. Less embellished with the merely rhetorical flourishes of these earlier works, it pursues a deeper analysis of civilization and its trappings by way of more rigorous argument, for the first time in a political and social idiom which marks the emergence of Rousseau’s philosophy of history in its most mature form. While it attracted some praise and even more hostility from reviewers in France, its greatest impact was probably first felt in Scotland, where Adam Smith was to cast his Theory of Moral Sentiments in part as a reply to it, and Lord Monboddo was to construct his case for the humanity of great apes in his Origin and Progress of Language in the light of propositions on this subject which it embraced. In Germany, both Kant in his Idea for a Universal History and Herder in his Ideas for a Philosophy of the History of Mankind were also to draw inspiration from its evolutionary doctrines – Kant particularly from its 44 distinction between the refinement of culture and the cultivation of morality, Herder most especially from its account of the social formation of language. In our own day Claude Lévi-Strauss has deemed it the inaugural Enlightenment contribution to the science of anthropology. Although it surveys a more remote antiquity than any of Rousseau’s other writings, it has come to be judged the most radical and progressive of his major works, certainly among those published in his lifetime. Part of the reason for its commanding that reputation is the critical manner of its assessment of earlier political doctrines, including both ancient and modern conceptions of natural law and contemporary theories of the social contract. While Condillac’s philosophy of language and Buffon’s natural history receive close attention as well and on Hobbes, Pufendorf, and Locke, above all, which are subjected to sharpest scrutiny and condemned at length by Rousseau in this text. He was convinced that these thinkers had provided an account of the sources of human depravity in terms which were quite generally correct, while misconceiving the true significance of their ideas. On the one hand, they had explained how men in the past might have been deluded into accepting those institutions which had made them morally corrupt, but, on the other hand, they believed that it was each man’s duty to uphold such institutions, on account of their providing solutions to another – for Rousseau entirely fictitious – problem. His rebuttal of Hobbes, Pufendorf, and Locke was pursued along roughly the following lines. In the exordium to the Discourse he contends that there must be two kinds of inequality among men, one which is natural or physical, and hence beyond our control, the other moral or political, because it depends upon human choice (P iii 131; G 131). There is, Rousseau observes, no fundamental link between these two types of inequality, for the claims to dominance put forward by the few who govern the many can have no force unless they are acknowledged to be proper, and that acknowledgement was granted by individuals to other persons 45 Human nature and civil society certain themes are taken to task, it is the political and social ideas of rather than bestowed as a gift of Nature. The moral and political divisions which obtain throughout the world are thus never to be justified with reference to any of the physical traits which mark individuals apart. If the opposite were true, then the exercise of force might itself create an obligation to obey, and men would somehow command the respect of their neighbours for the same reason that they arouse their fears. In the Social Contract Rousseau was to explain at greater length that force is not the foundation of right, and this is his position in the Discourse on Inequality as well. Together with other social contract theorists, he believed that the rules which differentiate persons in society could only come to prevail through their consent, so that, as he argues in Part i of this text, the inequalities produced by Nature must have been transformed into such inequalities as were enjoined by man Rousseau (P iii 160–1; G 158). 11. Frontispiece (‘Il retourne chez ses Egaux’) and title-page of the Discours sur l’inégalité (Amsterdam, 1755). 46 Rousseau conceived the central theme of his second Discourse as an account of how the human race might have undergone a transformation of this sort. Since in their natural state our ancestors would have had only casual and infrequent contact with each other, he claims that the earliest distinctions between individuals would have been of no consequence. The inequalities established by men themselves, however, formed the dominant features of each community (P iii 162, 193–4; G 159–60, 187–8). In their original condition, our forebears could have had ‘no moral relations with or determinate obligations to one another’ (P iii 152; G 150), and since natural man had neither any need for the company of other creatures like himself, nor any wish to hurt them, it was only with the birth of social institutions that his weakness became timidity or his strength a menace to his society, by contrast, where fixed and determinate relations do prevail, bind individuals together permanently through channels of subservience and command. Because they had been entirely mistaken in their conceptions of the state of nature, Hobbes, Pufendorf, and Locke, by contrast, had wrongly supposed that all individuals must there be equal in their powers, and each of these thinkers had imagined that as a consequence of this equality every person would be apprehensive of his neighbours and unable to live in safety among them. Men of equal abilities, Hobbes had alleged, could pursue the same objectives only at their peril, for without a common power to keep them in awe, they would be in a state of war (De cive, ch. 10; Leviathan, ch. 13). In order to achieve peace, men must institute an artificial superior or ‘mortal god’, he had supposed, commanding absolute authority to protect each person from the next, so that the pernicious effects of equality might be overcome through the subjection of the whole multitude to the Leviathan. Thus while for Rousseau the inequalities of the natural state must have been entirely without significance for mankind, according to Hobbes the fact that there must be equality in a masterless world was of great importance 47 Human nature and civil society neighbours. The inequalities which have arisen between persons in and was one of the reasons which made the attainment of peace there naturally impossible. For Pufendorf, similarly, men must have been precariously equal in their original condition. Agreeing with Hobbes that we were motivated by selfishness rather than any impulse of benevolence or fellowship, he nevertheless contended that in the state of nature we would have been at the mercy of the elements and of fierce animals, drawn together on account of our frailty and timidity, not positively but negatively, in order to survive (De jure naturæ et gentium, II iii 20). This was Pufendorf’s doctrine of socialitas or natural sociability – a trait which, he claimed, would have led our ancestors to form communities of ever-increasing complexity and sophistication, on account of the limitless capacities and insatiable desires unique to our species. The Rousseau growth of a political commonwealth would accordingly have been more gradual than Hobbes had imagined, but for Pufendorf it was similarly designed to overcome the perilous instability of our natural condition of equality through our acceptance of the rule of an absolute sovereign. Civil society or civilization, thus conceived, provided a remedy for the barbarous misery of our savage state. Kant would later term such a theory of the genesis of society the doctrine of ‘unsocial sociability’. For Locke, too, it had been the fundamental equality of men in their original condition, ‘wherein all power and jurisdiction is reciprocal’ (Second Treatise, ch. 2), which must have made the tenure of property there uncertain and insecure. Only in civil society, he supposed, where it was constantly defended by a superior power entrusted with its care, could private property be safeguarded and our natural right to it enforced. While Hobbes’s central focus had been the political dimension of peace, Pufendorf’s the collective need for security, and Locke’s the civil protection of property, the three writers appeared to be in agreement that individuals were naturally unable to survive in the absence of government, and thus that an artificial power must always 48 be established to reduce the dangers which accompany the unfettered equality of mankind. Rousseau’s account of inequality’s origins in his second Discourse was at least partly designed to contradict these claims. In his view, the superior authorities conceived by Hobbes, Pufendorf, and Locke must have reinforced the antagonisms which set persons apart from one another, and did not overcome such differences. He believed it was impossible to discover from the works of any of these or other political thinkers why men in the state of nature should seek protection from their neighbours, but he thought their ideas collectively did none the less explain how individuals might have established as legitimate just those determinate and fixed relations which form the distinctions between particular, it was true that men must have developed all their social obligations so as to protect their lives